Volume > Issue > The Return of Socrates

The Return of Socrates

The Unaborted Socrates: A Dramatic Debate on the Issues Surrounding Abortion

By Peter Kreeft

Publisher: InterVarsity Press

Pages: 155

Price: $4.95

Review Author: John F. Maguire

John F. Maguire is a Ph.D. candidate in sociology at the University of California at Berkeley, and a Contributing Editor of the NOR.

In his Operetti Morali Giacomo Leopardi de­scribes Socrates as having been “endowed with a very gentle temperament,” but as being “immea­surably ill-starred in his bodily form.” In Hellenic culture, a culture which had blended together the ideals of physical beauty and moral beauty, the misfortune of being disproportioned and “squat-faced,” as Socrates was, weighed heavily. And so it was that, born into a city “full of clamor, of pas­sions, of business, of pastimes, of wealth and other good things,” this marginal, sharp-witted, equivocal Athenian “very likely even in his youth despaired of being loved.”

A eugenic question mark, Socrates compen­sated by becoming a master of conversation, a vir­tuoso of dialectics. (Thus was born Greek moral philosophy, from which modern moral philosophy arose.) Ironically, the playful but exacting spirit that animated Socrates in his probings ultimately resulted in his falling under the official judgment of his own — the ruling — class: Socrates, unwant­ed tumor in the body politic.

In the modern world as in the ancient, the spirit we have come to call, “socratic” is suppress­ed. Today most institutional forms of civil dis­course preclude the socratic mode of dialogical in­quiry. Besides, people don’t have the time. “However much more patient the moderns may be than the ancients were,” writes Leopardi, “one would find no one today prepared to answer a thousand questions without pause, and listen to a hundred conclusions.”

But, happily, now comes Peter Kreeft, profes­sor of philosophy at Boston College, who has in hand, yes, some new dialogues in which Socrates figures centrally — dialogues, as it happens, just re­cently tape-recorded, for it appears that Socrates — thanks, I guess, to the favor of the gods — has re­turned to his native city, once again to gossip, daw­dle, pose questions, nettle, and provoke.

In contemporary Athens, however, Socrates (as Leopardi gave us reason to expect) has trouble getting a hearing. On one occasion as a guest at an international conference on law and morality, the sage of Atticus hears a speech in which the slogan “Every Child a Wanted Child” is bandied about. Of course Socrates wants to unpack the meaning of the terms “wanted” and “every child,” and so asks some questions from the floor, only to be told, stiffly, “We have a ten-minute time limit. Question­ers are requested to confine their remarks to two minutes each.” “Ah,” says Socrates, “it is indeed as the myths say: Kronos is the cruelest of all ty­rants.”

On another occasion Socrates wanders into an abortion clinic. An abortionist on the premises, af­ter a long exchange of views with Socrates, allows that he does not know whether the fetus is a per­son or not. This confession of ignorance, he hopes, will pacify Socrates, for does not the height of so­cratic wisdom consist in knowing that one is ignor­ant? Does it not consist in the “dissolution of knowledge into nothingness,” an “absolute negativ­ity,” as Kierkegaard thought? The answers is No: Kreeft’s Socrates, like Plato’s, “does not shelter — by means of irony’s disconcerting approach and perpetual denials — a joy of subjectivity conscious vanity of the world of objective knowledge freed of all hope of conquering the being of things,” as Jacques Maritain puts it. On the contrary, it is the actual being of the fetus that is the point of inquiry. The question of “is-ness,” as Kreeft’s Socrates calls it, is inescapable.

On the other hand, there exists a kind of care­lessness with respect to the question of the being of the fetus (or unborn infant). “Let’s see,” says Socrates to H., the abortionist at the clinic, “You do not know whether the fetus is a person, cor­rect?”

H.: “Correct.”

Socrates: “And your work here is to kill fetuses, correct?”

H.: “Socrates, I am continually shocked by the language you choose to use. I abort unwanted pregnancies.”

Socrates: “By killing fetuses or by some­thing else?”

H.: (Sigh.) “By killing fetuses.”

Socrates: “Not knowing whether they are persons or not?”

Socrates is practicing here his distinctive art — maieutics, the art of delivering minds — but this for the moment only insofar as he wants to show that those who justify lethal interventions in the normal delivery process of pregnancy display an abandoned or reckless disinterest in the question of the ontological status of the fetus.

But Socrates goes on to put his maieutics to affirmative use. Against the proposition that a fe­tus is not a person because it is not rational, Socra­tes affirms a difference between being something and functioning as something. The human person, he points out, is that which functions (reasons); it is not this functionality itself. Nor is the human person identical to its genetic code; “the code is of or for something” — and this something is properly called the human person.

On the basis of this distinction between being and function, between person and life, Kreeft’s Socrates argues that “the fact that the fetus does not yet function as a person does not prove it is not a person.” It seems to me, however, that for the sake of precision Socrates should have argued that the fact that the fetus is not yet functioning rationally does not prove that it is not a person. In actual fact, there is a sense in which the fetus al­ways functions as a person: as, precisely, a person in the fetal stage of development. Personality is the very being of the developing man; all human func­tions belong to the human person, because, as Kreeft and his Socrates say, it is the human person who properly is.

As drama, Kreeft’s dialogues are not high po­etry. The decision to call one of the discussants (the abortionist I have called “H.”) “Doctor Rex Herrod” (intentionally spelled thus by Kreeft) is a mistake both dramaturgically and philosophically. Truly Herodian men are beyond dialogue, as Mar­tin Buber once said of Hitler and his ilk; against them, we turn to the weapon of prophetic denun­ciation.

This leads me, however, to speak of a point at which socratic rationalism seems to be wanting in caution. It elides the element of malice. It tends to reduce morality to knowledge, with the upshot that it is assumed that every fault comes from ig­norance. Malice, as I say, is missed. It is possible, I am saying, that one’s heart can be too hardened to participate in dialogue. It seems that today’s Hero­dian slaughter of the innocents involves something more than intellectual blindness.

An intriguing book, Peter Kreeft’s The Unaborted Socrates is easy reading. Most of the argu­ments for and against abortion find their way into the dialogues. The tyrant Kronos will not waste away the reader who ponders these exchanges.

Enjoyed reading this?

READ MORE! REGISTER TODAY

SUBSCRIBE

You May Also Enjoy

Pro-Abortion & Anti-War?

If you are anti-war and pro-abortion, and you won't recognize that you are making war on the unborn, you are not really anti-war.

Times Square Journal: If 'My Body Is My Own,' Why Not Sell It?

Ed. Note: For a week in early May in New York, Operation Rescue conducted the…

Ebenezer Scrooge at Christmas Today

Scrooge stated, “Let those poor go to the prisons and the Union workhouses. And if they’d rather die, they had better do it."