April 1990
Salvaging Teilhard de Chardin
In spite of wincing a bit at Will Hoyt’s occasional slur (e.g., referring to Teilhard de Chardin’s thought as “sophomoric”), I found his essay on Chardin’s The Phenomenon of Man (Jan.-Feb.) thoughtful and provocative. Yet in the end Hoyt was better at showing us the limitations of Chardin’s thought than at suggesting what might be of lasting value.
Essentially, Hoyt seems to have four objections to Chardin’s theory. First, he points out that Chardin suffers from the general liberal, “enlightened” tendency to take sin too lightly. Liberalism fails to see clearly the sinful distortions of the modern mentality. That Hiroshima, the Gulag, and the Holocaust “stand in a more integral relationship to the energies of science and reason and enlightenment than Teilhard might want to admit” is a point well made. Second, he cautions us that one possible outcome of Chardin’s type of thinking might be a very unsavory type of social Darwinism. Yet, while this seems possible, we might arrive at a very different outcome if we were to hypothesize that the culture most fit to survive is the one that best incarnates the reality of love in the social order. Third, he questions Chardin’s optimistic view that, “There is no question of shipwreck.” Of course, many shipwrecks are possible. Fourth, he warns us against believing in the salvific role of science and technology. As a “mental health” professional, I could not agree more with his judgment that “handing over the welfare of society at large to scientists is frightening.”
Agreeing in large part, then, that the bath water is in fact rather murky in places, and perhaps even toxic, I would nevertheless suggest that there may still be a baby in Chardin’s writing that is worth preserving. Chardin confronts us clearly and forcefully with two of the most central tasks that must be addressed if Christianity and culture are to enter into a productive and meaningful relationship. First, we must somehow overcome the estrangement between the outer and the inner, between fact and meaning, if our individual and collective psyche is not to continue in a state of almost psychotic bifurcation. Second, we must accept the facts of evolution (but not necessarily the modern reductionistic interpretation of them), and explicate the inner spiritual significance of these facts through a process that is hermeneutically sound. As Ezekiel interpreted the meaning of the exile in the image of the dry bones, for example, so we must interpret evolution in terms of Christian images that disclose its meaning for us. Although Chardin has not accomplished these two tasks with complete adequacy, he has provided us with some useful points of departure.
It is my conjecture that much of the fragmentation of modern life derives from a lack of understanding of how language systems work. The language of science and technology is the language of fact. But fact stripped of meaning is useless. Fact enables us to manipulate, but not to set or critique goals. To live meaningfully we also need the language of prophecy and poetry. We must learn to bring both language systems into focus on a single subject — such as Chardin attempted to do with evolution.
Jim Hunter
Church of St. Jude
Lincoln, Maine
Exciting Horizons
As a consequence of reading your editorial (Jan.-Feb.) entitled “The Crumbling of Communism: Good for the Catholic Church?,” I have decided to decline a subscription to your magazine.
The predominance of quotations from Cardinal Ratzinger immediately alerted me to the nature of the editorial as taking a defensive attitude toward the Church, and as not at all being in the generous and open spirit of Vatican II. So it is logical that “free choice and pluralism” are understood as threats rather than as invitations to more deeply appreciate how the Lord continues to reveal Himself in the living experience of His people, the starting point of all theology.
Furthermore, the editor rejects the priority of conscience as the ultimate guide for moral choices, and suffers from a severe lack of discernment by lumping together the moral issues of abortion, homosexuality, remarriage, and alternate lifestyles. For example, is it not possible for two persons of the same sex to live and love together in the context of Christian commitment and yet be opposed to abortion?
Rather than an anxious Church that “relentlessly gazes at the sirens on waves ahead,” may we walk across the waves with the assurance of a Christ whose hand is always extended in the challenge of new and exciting horizons.
James Andrew
Karen Catholic Worker House
Somerville, Massachusetts
The NOR’s Jan.-Feb. editorial connects consumerism in the West with Protestant Christians who “shop” for the church that pleases them. I don’t think the two are connected.
The “consumer sovereignty” enjoyed by Protestants is more aptly portrayed as the quest for appropriate sociocultural expressions of belief in the reality of Christ.
Peter Loan
Washington, D.C.
Truth Not Cost-Effective
It is one of those great moments when you read an essay and sense that another pilgrim has seen what your eyes, your heart sees. The NOR’s Jan.-Feb. editorial was such a moment for me.
When a disciple of the revealed Lord Jesus attempts to live out the gift of faith with a heart “schooled” by our consumerist culture, conflict will arise. During my three years of seminary, this conflict offered us all, students and faculty, a steady dose of tension.
Dealing with various tensions is part of living, and must be part of priestly formation. The tragedy is that many who have been given the opportunity to form new priests in the living faith of the Church do not realize what your editorial asserts: that the Way of the Lord Jesus is given from beyond us. Our proclivity to regard truth in cost-effective terms betrays what revelation is all about.
Fr. David P. Talley
Atlanta, Georgia
On Pacifism & Anarchism
Stuart Gudowitz’s review of my anthology, A Revolution of the Heart: Essays on the Catholic Worker (Dec.), deserves some correction.
In his attempt to critique the pacifism and anarchism of the Catholic Worker movement, Gudowitz writes: “Curiously, in their essay, ‘Houses of Hospitality: A Pilgrimage into Nonviolence,’ Angie O’Gorman and Patrick Coy state that, even at the New York City Catholic Worker during [Dorothy] Day’s lifetime, police were occasionally called in to deal with violent guests.”
Gudowitz would evidently have the Worker throw out its commitment to pacifism and anarchism simply because individual Workers have often met with failure in their application of these principles in the often violent atmosphere of hospitality houses. Gudowitz apparently requires pacifism and anarchism to be mistake-proof.
The nonviolence of pacifism and the individual responsibility of anarchism do sometimes fail. Few know this truth better than those engaged in experimenting with these principles in hospitality houses. As Angie O’Gorman and I reported in some detail, when failures occur, Workers do on occasion turn to physical force, coercion, and the police to restore order, if not to obtain resolution leading to reconciliation. Since violence and state power also frequently fail, logic suggests that Gudowitz would demand that they be abandoned as well. Is he ready to do so?
More serious is Gudowitz’s assertion that “not even their own experience seems to have caused the Workers to rethink their pacifism or anarchism.” Even a cursory glance at our chapter shows it to be an attempt to do precisely that.
Not only do Angie and I do so, but we include example after example of past and present Catholic Workers reflecting, in interviews with us or in the pages of their respective house newspapers, on the successes and failures of the Worker experiment with nonviolence and individual responsibility. Sifting through a long and rich experiment, we probe for patterns as to when nonviolence works and when it has failed, and what dynamics contribute to bringing a particular success or failure into being.
Unlike Gudowitz, the Catholic Worker movement is not ready to abandon what it perceives to be the gospel call to nonviolence and individual responsibility simply because it may sometimes fail. But for the reviewer to maintain that the movement has been unwilling to reflect on its daily application of the theory is to demonstrate an ignorance of not only the movement, but of our chapter as well.
Patrick G. Coy
St. Louis, Missouri
To Fight a Nuclear War
Regarding C.H. Ross’s review of my book, A Fighting Chance (Jan.-Feb.): Ross is right that the “decisive question” in the debate over nuclear weapons is whether a policy of deterrence “necessarily involves the intent to launch a nuclear attack against the enemy’s civilian population.” However, at this point the book I wrote, and the book Ross evidently read, differ as night from day.
I tried to make clear that the execution of such an attack is both immoral and unnecessary. Beyond that, I tried to make clear that while the threat of such an attack might be moral (I really did not argue either way), the effect of such a threat would be to drive moral people out of our military services. Therefore, I argued, we should not make such a threat, both because of its detrimental effect on our military, and because we could not morally execute it should we be attacked.
Despite what I actually wrote, Ross describes me as “highly impatient with the suggestion that deterrence is possible without such intent.” I plead not guilty. On the contrary, I am highly impatient with those who take it for granted that deterrence requires a threat against civilians.
If we don’t threaten civilians, then who or what should we threaten? Ross did get it right this time. I do advocate a “war fighting” posture. I argue that we can best deter war by being prepared to defeat an enemy before we are annihilated, rather than threatening to annihilate him after he has annihilated us.
The requirements for such a posture include weapons which can be used in a discriminating and proportionate manner, and a Command and Control system capable of directing their use in that manner. I considered these topics so important that I devoted a chapter to each.
I argue that these conditions are difficult to meet, but that we can meet them if we try. Ross evidently believes otherwise. He postulates a scenario in which a “harried, outnumbered” NATO commander is surrounded and in danger of being overwhelmed, and suggests that the commander may decide to incinerate, say, Prague.
Two points need to be made. First, such a commander is unlikely to possess weapons which can reach Prague. Those long-range weapons will be based to the rear, out of immediate danger. He will instead possess short-range tactical weapons. Second, what good would it do him to incinerate Prague? His immediate problem is the enemy troops in contact with his forces. It is against those forces which he can and must direct his nuclear weapons. The real danger is not that he will incinerate Prague, but that he will incinerate some small village a kilometer or two away from him, because an enemy tank column is passing through it. It is against this possibility that we must guard.
Here Ross seems unnecessarily pessimistic. He asserts, “the battlefield is a notoriously poor breeding place for rational moral decisions.” This depends on the kind of people we recruit for our military services, and the kind of training we give them before they reach the battlefield. To argue that no one can make moral decisions in the heat of battle (i.e., don’t kill prisoners; make an effort to avoid killing civilians) smacks of an unwarranted determinism. Traditions of chivalry, and of sanctuary for noncombatants, have been observed in the past. We are obliged to try their equivalents today, rather than give up in despair.
Finally, Ross asserts that I haven’t told the reader how to “bell the cat,” that is, I haven’t prescribed in detail how to use nuclear weapons in a discriminating and proportionate manner. I have provided more detail than his review gives me credit for, but essentially he is correct. There were two reasons for this shortcoming.
First, the almost universally prevalent opinion is that deterrence necessarily means threats against civilians. Even John Paul II, in his public statements, assumes that “nuclear war” means attacks on cities. He states that “deterrence,” based on such a threat, is tolerable only as a step toward complete disarmament. In short, I saw as my chief task the need to counter this idea; to argue that nuclear weapons need not be used against civilians but can be used in a discriminating and proportionate manner against purely military targets.
Second, because of this prevalent assumption, little thought has been given to “war fighting.” The very idea of preparing to fight a nuclear war is immediately condemned as “making nuclear war thinkable,” or worse, as trying to provoke a nuclear war. We need to think about how to fight a nuclear war: weapons, tactics, Command and Control, political restraints. This won’t happen unless we first recognize that “war fighting” is both possible and necessary.
Joseph P. Martino
Sidney, Ohio
You May Also Enjoy
The world does not like seriously religious people, like conservative rural white American Christians and like the Ultra-Orthodox Jews.
I am still struggling with the phenomenon of the so-called underclass — struggling with the…
The history of liturgical reform that led to the promulgation of the New Mass predated Vatican II by several decades.